We're now going to jump forward in time about
two thousand years and consider an entirely different set of philosophical
questions.
The history of western thought is usually
divided into four main periods, the ancient,
mediaeval, modern, and contemporary periods. We've been studying
the ancient period and now we're going to move past the mediaeval period
and into the modern period. The mediaeval philosophers were concerned
with a very wide range of philosophical questions, but the focus of
many of them was what we might call metaphysical and/or theological.
These questions largely concerned the nature of the universe, how things
are set up in the cosmos, what part God plays in everything, how human
beings should act in order to be aligned with the ultimate laws of
being, and so on. These philosophies made claims about the ultimate
nature of being, about God, about human beings' place in the cosmos,
and similar themes.
At the beginning of the modern period, though,
some philosophers began to question these claims and to wonder how
anyone could know whether they were true or not. This led to their
wondering how it is that human beings can know anything, and then to
trying to figure out what counts as true and real knowledge as opposed
to mere opinion or belief. This philosophical effort came to be termed "epistemology."
For example, consider the claim that the
earth is round. You would perhaps say that you "know" the
earth is round rather than that you just "believe" the earth
is round, or that it is merely your "opinion" that the earth
is round. But what would you say is the basis for your knowing that?
On what is your knowledge about the shape of the earth founded? You
have probably not personally been far enough away from the earth to
actually see its roundness, so your knowledge is probably not based
on direct personal experience. Perhaps you have seen photographs of
the earth from a distance, but then in that case you are relying on
what other people tell you about those photographs, that they are actually
photographs of the earth, that they have not been tampered with to
make the earth appear round, etc. So your knowledge about the roundness
of the earth is partly grounded in your acceptance of the claims of
some people you take to be trustable authorities. You choose to believe
what they tell you. So your "knowing" about the shape of
the earth is partly grounded on some "beliefs" you choose
to accept.
The fact that many other people, or even
that most other people, share your beliefs does not actually increase
the likelihood that your beliefs are true. We all know of beliefs that
almost everyone in the past used to hold: for example, almost everyone
used to believe the earth was flat, that the universe was only four
or five thousand years old, that women and slaves were inferior to
adult males, and so on. These beliefs are now not held by most people.
Perhaps we should be asking ourselves what beliefs we have today that
in a century or two will be considered not worthy of belief.
In any case, epistemology is the study of
how we know, what true knowledge is and what it is founded on, what
the differences might be between knowledge, belief and opinion, and
whether we can know anything at all with certitude.
The word "epistemology" derives
from the Greek word episteme, knowledge. Epistemology is the ology,
study of, what knowledge is and what it is grounded on. (The Greek
word sophia means "wisdom," and the word gnosis means "understanding," as
in the phrase gnothi seauton, "know thyself," or better: "understand
thyself.") The word episteme refers to what we might call
simple information, data, or "factual" knowledge. That is,
it refers not to what we would call wisdom and not to what we would
call deep understanding, but refers instead to knowledge of simple
factual data. For example: How many stories tall is the Sears Tower?
What biological functions does the kidney serve? What are the main
differences between tropical and desert vegetations? What is the second
law of thermodynamics? and so on.
So epistemology wants us to be continually
questioning what we think we "know," and wants us to be asking
ourselves what our knowledge is founded on, etc.
For example, do you know what you ate for
dinner yesterday? If you do know, what would you say that knowledge
is based on? Perhaps you will say it is based on your direct experience
of eating it, but the more accurate answer should probably be that
your knowledge is based on a memory experience you are presently having,
a memory experience which feels like it is an accurate memory of an
experience you had yesterday. But can our memories ever be mistaken
about something that happened yesterday? Is it possible for a person
to have a false memory about something they believe happened in the
past? Suppose you decide to trust your memory in this case, though.
If you do, then what you are in effect doing is deciding to "believe" what
your memory is telling you. So in effect your "knowledge" about
yesterday's dinner is based on a "belief" you choose to have
about the accuracy of your present memory. Your belief about your memory's
accuracy may turn out to be mistaken in this case (you know your memory
has been mistaken sometimes in the past when you originally thought
that it was remembering correctly.) And yet, despite the fact that
we all know memories can be mistaken even when they feel like they
are being accurate, you are presently choosing to believe in the accuracy
of your memory about yesterday's dinner. How does a person decide when
to trust their memory and when not to?
Now most people do not like the idea of trying
to question everything they know or believe. The epistemologists understand
this, but they also understand how important it is to try to find out
what is actually, really true in the world. It is important in the
sciences, in the study of history, in psychology and sociology, and
even in daily events in the world. What really actually did happen
between Clarence Thomas and Anita Hill, for example? How does the human
immune system really work? How does the brain actually work? Do breast
implants cause autoimmune diseases or not? Do pesticide residues cause
cancers and neurological diseases? Will it be possible to make an effective
HIV vaccine? And so on. We would rather know the actual truth about
these things, and not have to rely only on opinions or beliefs.
Perhaps the most fruitful way to approach
some of the epistemological questions we will be exploring this quarter
will be to try questioning some of the beliefs that we never question,
beliefs that we all have and hold because they seem so obvious to us.
Let's consider a few examples of these common beliefs.
1. Time
Most people in the western world believe
that time is real, that it is not a human construct, and that it
actually exists out there in the world rather than just in our brains. As
we will see when we discuss the work of Immanuel Kant (and others),
there are some very important reasons to doubt whether this belief
is true or not.
2. We're here
Most people believe that they are actually
situated right where they think they are. You probably believe that
you are actually sitting right there in the room and reading this text
right now. You may have no doubts about that at all. And yet it is
possible that that belief is completely wrong. It may be the case that
you are not actually there right now at all, but are actually asleep
in your bed and only dreaming that you are there. During a dream you
are usually just as fully convinced that what you are experiencing
is real as you are convinced right now that what you are experiencing
is real. It is not always possible to distinguish between what is a
dream and what is reality.
Or perhaps it may be the case that you are
actually sitting in someone's office right now and that you have just
been hypnotized to believe that you are sitting at home reading. Anyone
who has ever been hypnotized realizes how complete and real those illusion
can be.
It may be the case, in other words, that
what you take to be an obvious fact -- viz., that you are sitting and
reading in that room right now -- may actually turn out to be only
an illusion. You may not actually be where you think you are.
3. Stuff exists
Most people believe that physical material
things -- what I will call "stuff" -- actually exists. This
seems to be one of our most cherished beliefs in the modern world,
the belief in the real existence of physical matter. We moderns might
truthfully be termed "materialists," in the sense that we
believe so dogmatically in the existence of physical matter.
This belief in the physical existence of
material things is so deeply ingrained in us -- it is even built into
the very structure of many (but not all) languages -- that it seems
unquestionably obvious. We cannot imagine how anyone with any sense
could even consider doubting that physical material things exist.
The belief in physical material stuff is
a dogma with us. We hold this belief dogmatically and unquestioningly,
and we consider it laughable and foolish that anyone would question
it. (In much the same way the flatness of the earth seemed patently
obvious to everyone a few centuries ago, and it was thought that only
fools would question it.)
What does it mean to hold to a belief dogmatically?
It means that we hold to it unquestioningly and we consider it foolish
and wrong to doubt that belief. (Not all dogmas are religious ones,
of course; many kinds of beliefs are held dogmatically and unquestioningly.)
One indication that a belief is a dogmatic one for you is if you find
it ludicrous that someone would ever question it, or if it makes you
slightly irritated when someone seriously calls it into question. People
do not like to have their dogmatic beliefs questioned.
What the epistemologists would want us to
do is to be willing to examine and question all of our beliefs,
especially the ones we most take for granted, and those to which we
have become most strongly attached. Unless we are willing to question
these beliefs, we will not ever make progress in our understanding
of the world. It was important, for example, to question our dogmatic
belief in the flatness of the earth, and also to question our dogmatic
belief that the earth was the center of the universe. Without questioning
even these most obvious beliefs, beliefs that virtually everyone held,
we would never have made any progress in our understanding of the world.
Our next class project, then, will be to
try to seriously question one of our most cherished beliefs probably
a dogmatic belief for many people - that physical stuff exists.
To help in this effort, you can turn now to the mini-lecture "On
Stuff."